[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

[RT] GEN: MORE ON MISES SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS



PureBytes Links

Trading Reference Links




 
----- Original Message ----- 
From: <A 
href="" title=article@xxxxxxxxx>Mises Daily Article 

To: <A href="" 
title=article@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>Mises Daily Article 
Sent: Wednesday, August 06, 2003 7:20 AM
Subject: Mises and His School 

<A 
href="">http://www.mises.org/fullstory.asp?control=1291
 
Mises 
and His School 
by J.G. 
Hülsmann
[Posted August 6, 2003]
This is the opening lecture to 
the <A 
href=""><FONT 
face="Verdana, Helvetica" size=2>Mises University<FONT 
face="Verdana, Helvetica" size=2>, delivered August 3, 2003
<IMG align=right alt="" border=0 
src="">What is Austrian Economics? 
A few years ago, at the University of Paris, I gave a course with the title 
"Introduction to Austrian Economics." It turned out that some of the students 
who signed up for the course believed it was meant to deal with business 
conditions in the country that lies between Germany, Switzerland, Italy, 
Hungary, Slovakia, and the Czech Republic. They were very surprised by the 
content of my lectures. To be fair, it must be said that one of them stayed on 
throughout the course. One lady was glad to discover that Austria had brought 
forth a school of economic thought that up to the present day enjoys a living 
tradition in the entire world.
Austrian Economics is a body of ideas, 
and we are here this week to study these ideas. That in itself is already an 
exciting and instructive activity. After all, the history of ideas is a 
fascinating subject. However, I take it that most of you have not come to Auburn 
because you are merely interested in ideas as such. You are interested in ideas 
that are true&#8212;ideas that properly reflect the workings of the real world to 
which they refer. You are interested in gaining an adequate understanding of the 
world of social relationships, and in sharpening your judgment in political 
matters.
If this is what you desire, you have 
come to the right place. The faculty of our summer university is not a group of 
bookish scholars that share an antiquarian interest in the history of ideas. 
Rather, they are intellectuals who not only believe that ideas make a difference 
in society and politics, but who are firmly convinced that ideas alone reign 
supreme when it comes to political decision-making; and that, therefore, it is 
of crucial importance for the welfare of our families, regions, nations, and all 
of mankind that the best available knowledge be applied in matters 
political.
The reason for the existence of the 
Mises Institute is that the works of its name patron, Ludwig von Mises, are the 
best available foundation for an adequate understanding of the issues involved 
in political decision making. In a word, the very point of Austrian Economics, 
as embodied in the works of Mises, is that it is the foremost political science 
of our day. It is far more systematic, rigorous, and penetrating than anything 
else in the field.
This is also the conviction of the 
faculty assembled here to instruct you during the coming week. This does not 
mean that we agree among ourselves on each single issue, and neither does it 
mean that we agree with Mises on all issues. Science is after all very much a 
work in progress. It does not provide ultimate answers such as revealed 
religion. It is only a special way, even though a very powerful way, to find 
guidance for our actions.
In a word, the works of Mises are not 
something like holy writ for our faculty, and neither should they be for you. 
But they are a precious starting point for further explorations and critical 
corrections, and a rich fountain of inspiration.
Who Was Mises
Ludwig von Mises was born in 1881 in 
Lemberg, a provincial capital of what was at the time the second-largest country 
of Europe: Austria-Hungary. His father was a railroad engineer in Lemberg who 
had married a lady from a bourgeois family in Vienna, the capital of the 
country. Both parents were Jews and Mises too received the standard religious 
education. Let me mention in this context that, although he later became 
agnostic, he never lost his respect for religious life. In many of his writings 
and correspondence he also stressed that there was no contradiction whatever 
between libertarian political views and faith.
When Ludwig was still a small boy, the 
family moved to Vienna, where his father had obtained employment in the railroad 
ministry. At the age of eleven, Ludwig entered some sort of an early-age 
college, where during the next eight years he received a humanistic education. 
The main subjects taught were Latin (eight hours per week) and Greek (six 
hours).
Young Ludwig had at that point already 
developed a vigorous interest in history and politics. He devoured a great 
number of books on various periods of the history of his country, and it was in 
these years that he developed the spirit of criticism that is so essential for 
scientific work and which served him well during the rest of his life. The 
interest he displayed for the history of his own country, and more specifically 
for contemporary history, foreshadowed much of his later intellectual 
development. He was not interested in history merely for its own sake. The point 
was to learn from the past the lessons necessary to guide action here and 
now.
When Mises finished school at the age 
of nineteen, therefore, he signed up as a student at the department of law and 
government science at the University of Vienna, which in those days was one of 
the top universities in the entire world. He joined the seminar of Carl 
Grünberg, an economic historian who studied the evolution of peasant life in 
Eastern Europe. Grünberg had him write a dissertation on the conditions leading 
to the liberation of peasants in Galicia, the province in which Mises was born. 
It was his first academic work and so impressive in the eyes of his professors 
that it was immediately published as a monograph by the university 
press.
Mises continued to study the economic 
condition of the working classes, and under the guidance of Grünberg he learned 
to understand history as resulting from the interplay of special interests. This 
bode him well for the rest of his life. In his later works on economic theory, 
Mises accorded due attention to "the clash of group interests," as he called it, 
something that distinguished him from many other theorists.
Thus Mises started off as an economic 
historian, and he very probably would have become a great champion of the 
so-called Historical School of Economics, which dominated in those days the 
social-science departments in Germany and Austria. But then something unexpected 
happened that turned him away from fact gathering, as it was practised by the 
Historical School, and toward the study of economic theory. Around Christmas of 
1903, Mises had his first exposure to Austrian Economics when he read Carl 
Menger's Principles of Economics.
He later said that it was this reading 
that turned him into an economist. For the rest of his life, Mises would say 
that books are the best university. This one book certainly made a huge 
difference in his life.
Menger convinced Mises that historical 
research, important though it was, did not cover all layers of social reality. 
There was an entire universe of things that played a crucial role in human 
conduct, but which could not be grasped by empirical field studies or archival 
work. Scarcity, value, intentions, choice, error, and uncertainty were such 
things. They could only be grasped through an intellectual process of reflection 
or meditation, and knowledge about these things was not "history," but 
"theory."
After reading Menger, Mises turned 
back to the great classic works of economic science, to Hume, Smith, Say, and 
Ricardo. And he came to see that theory was not merely necessary for a full 
understanding of human behavior, but also that theory alone provided a firm 
guidance in all practical matters, in particular, in political 
decisionmaking.
The Historical School could not offer 
such guidance. One of its critics, writing in Mises's day, said that the method 
of this school verged on the absurd. "They go into workers' apartments, measure 
the surface, and then claim that they are too small." (Ludwig Pohle) But by 
which standards were the apartments too small? And even if one came to agree 
that the living conditions of workers were not very good by some absolute 
standard, it was not at all clear which political consequences this entailed. 
For the crucial question was whether government interventions could improve 
these conditions at all. Historical enquiry could not answer this question, 
theory could.
Hence, Mises became a theoretician&#8212;in 
fact, the foremost economic theoretician of the 20th century&#8212;not for the sake of 
intellectual pleasure derived from playing with constructions of his own making. 
He had no talent to be some sort of an early game theorist or 
general-equilibrium model builder. He became a theoretician because Menger had 
shown that theory could describe a part of reality that was not covered by any 
other type of knowledge. In short, it was Mises's quest for greater realism and 
his interest in practical questions that led him to study and develop pure 
theory in the way Carl Menger had done it before him.
When Mises became interested in 
Menger's work, Menger himself had already retired from the University of Vienna. 
He had left the field to his two most important disciples, both of whom taught 
at this University from 1905 onwards. Their names were Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk and 
Friedrich von Wieser.
Wieser's work was inspired at least as 
much by the Englishmen Jevons as it was based on Menger's Principles. 
Like Jevons, indeed, much like present-day theoreticians, Wieser made in his 
theories ample use of fictions. The central element of his economic thought was 
the concept of "natural value." This type of value had nothing to do with the 
wealth of any concrete acting person, and it was objective in the sense that it 
was the same for all persons.
Yet although his analysis of value was 
much less realistic than Menger's, Wieser felt no inhibitions to derive sweeping 
political conclusions from his constructions. The fact that real-life economies 
were necessarily different from economies in which natural value reigned, did in 
his eyes not count against his theory; it counted against the real world. He saw 
in his brainchild of natural value an economic ideal and recommended that 
economic policy should make sure that all factors of production be 
treated according to their natural values. According to Wieser, this might be 
achieved in a perfect communist state. But it might also be achieved through 
heavy government intervention in the market economy.
In his early years, Mises was very 
sympathetic to Wieser's policy stance, but he was not at all impressed with his 
lack of realism. Rather than attending any one of Wieser's classes, Mises 
attended the classes of the man who seemed to represent most faithfully the 
Mengerian legacy, and who was also in Carl Menger's own judgment his most 
important follower.
Starting in the fall of 1905, Eugen 
von Böhm-Bawerk conducted a graduate seminar at the University of Vienna. He had 
just retired from his position as a Minister of Finance and dedicated the last 
years of his life (he died in 1914) to research and writing, and also to some 
debating in the Austrian House of Lords. Mises graduated in early 1906, but he 
continued to attend Böhm-Bawerk's seminar until the very end. It was here that 
he received his final polish as an economics student and, most importantly, it 
was here that he formed his ideas about what a professor should be 
like.
At the same time, Mises did the 
research on his first great theoretical treatise in the Mengerian spirit, the 
Theory of Money and Credit. Let me mention in passing that Mises could 
work on the project only in the evening and night hours. He never found a full 
paid university position in Vienna, and therefore had to earn a living with 
other activities. In 1909, he accepted a job at the local chamber of commerce 
and remained an employee until he left Vienna in 1934, when he finally did 
obtain a university chair&#8212;in Geneva, Switzerland.
After some five years of hard work in 
his spare-time, then, Mises published his treatise on money in 1912. Some 
sixteen other books would follow in the coming years and decades. But the money 
book belonged to the four truly great books that he had written and which every 
student of Austrian Economics should read. The other three great books have the 
titles Socialism (first published in 1922), Human Action 
(1940/1949), and Theory and History (1956).
Money
In the Theory of Money and 
Credit, Mises demonstrated that Carl Menger's value theory could also be 
applied to the case of money. Menger himself, as well as Böhm-Bawerk, had left 
money out of their considerations. Following the classical economists&#8212;Hume, 
Smith, Say, Ricardo, Mill&#8212;they had assumed that, ultimately, money does not have 
an impact on the wealth of nations; real factors alone determine productivity 
and incomes.
Critics of the Austrian School had 
argued that this neglect was a rather serious shortcoming. Money was in fact 
quite unlike all the other goods when it came to the relationship between value 
and price. In the case of other goods, the price resulted from the interaction 
of the subjective values of different individuals. Value was the cause of price. 
But in the case of money, there was no such one-sided causal determination. The 
value of money certainly had some impact on the formation of money prices, but 
money prices were themselves causes of the value of money. A unit of money with 
a higher purchasing power was after all more valuable, ceteris paribus, 
than a unit with a lower purchasing power. But if this was true, there seemed to 
be an inescapable circle: the value of money determined money prices, and these 
prices in turn determined the value of money&#8212;some sort of a chicken-egg 
problem.
The first Austrian to take up the 
challenge was Friedrich von Wieser, but unfortunately he again came up with a 
theoretical construct based by and large on fiction. The challenge had remained 
unanswered.
It was in this situation that Mises 
stepped in and provided a truly Mengerian "realist" solution. He showed that the 
use of money was determined by marginal value, just as the use of any other 
good. The key to his demonstration was the regression theorem. Mises argued that 
the circle in the explanation of money prices was only apparent. It was not the 
case that marginal value determined the formation of money prices, and that 
these very same money prices in some sort of a feedback process determined the 
values from which they had sprung. Rather there was a time component in the 
chain of causation. Market participants relied in their present value judgments 
on the money prices of the past, not on the money prices that in the 
present resulted from those present value judgments.
But what about those past money 
prices? How did they come into existence? Through the same process. They 
resulted from value judgments that relied on money prices existing even further 
back in time. The same explanation could be applied to all money prices existing 
in times past. Each time one had to go back to somewhat older prices.
But was this not an infinite 
regression&#8212;and thus a nonexplanation? Mises argued this was not the case. If one 
went back far enough, one would reach the point at which money emerged from some 
pre-existing commodity that had not been used in indirect exchange. At this 
point, money prices would result from values that were based on the nonmonetary 
uses of these commodities.
Mises's regression theorem has 
remained one of the core elements of Austrian price theory, and more recently it 
has found an important new application in the field of currency competition. 
Indeed, the regression theorem tells us that it is impossible to launch a new 
paper money in the way one would launch any other new product on the market. 
Nobody would have any idea about the purchasing power of such a new paper money, 
precisely because it is new, and thus the market participants could not evaluate 
it.
Mises made other important 
contributions in his Theory of Money and Credit. He delivered a thorough 
analysis of the redistribution effects that go hand in hand with changes in the 
money supply. Additional quantities of money reach certain individuals first and 
allow them to bid up prices and thus to buy commodities that would otherwise 
have been bought by other market participants. It follows that money is never 
neutral. It has a profound impact on the allocation of resources through time 
and space.
But the single best-known contribution 
of the Theory of Money and Credit is probably its business-cycle theory, 
which Mises called the circulation-credit theory of the business cycle and which 
is today usually called the Austrian theory of the business cycle. Mises argued 
that the business cycle results from fractional-reserve banking. Under a 
fractional-reserve banking system, bankers can create money substitutes ex 
nihilo and give these substitutes to their customers in the form of 
fiduciary credit or circulation credit.
When this happens, the new supply of 
fiduciary credit reduces interest rates below the equilibrium level. This in 
turn distorts entrepreneurial calculations. At the lower interest rate, more 
investment projects appear to be profitable than would otherwise have been the 
case. But this impression is fallacious because the quantities of real resources 
have not increased. It is not possible to complete any additional investments 
projects. If entrepreneurs, deluded by the increased availability of fiduciary 
credit, launch new investment projects, they squander resources and set the 
economy on a crash course. It is physically impossible to complete all the 
projects that have been started, because there are just not enough real 
resources. Sooner or later a decision must be made where to put the available 
resources; all other projects must be abandoned. This is what happens in the 
bust phase of the business cycle.
Let me draw your attention to the 
implications of this theory for the interpretation of the boom phase and the 
so-called bust phase of the business cycle. In the popular mind, the boom is a 
period of growth&#8212;certainly an exuberant growth, but growth nevertheless. And the 
bust is a period of stagnation and destruction.
By contrast, in the light of Mises's 
business cycle theory, one understands that the apparent improvement of things 
in the boom is just that&#8212;an illusion. What really happens is that scarce 
resources are wasted and society as a whole is therefore objectively 
impoverished. The illusion springs from the fact that the wasting goes hand in 
hand with a simultaneous redistribution process (remember: money is not 
neutral). Some members of society do improve their lot during the boom, 
and because public attention is on these happy fates, the general impoverishment 
goes unnoticed.
Similarly, the bust or&#8212;as it is 
sometimes called&#8212;the crisis is not, as in the popular perception, the beginning 
of all trouble. Rather, it is the beginning of a new sanity. The outbreak of the 
crisis occurs at the very moment when entrepreneurial fantasies meet the hard 
rock of economic reality, and finally cease. Entrepreneurs now abandon projects 
that cannot be continued with the available resources, and they watch out for 
new projects that are better adapted to present conditions. There is some 
stagnation in a crisis, but from the point of view of the Austrian business 
cycle theory, stagnation is certainly better than a continued boom, because 
after all it does not waste resources.
Socialism
The next major contribution that needs 
to be mentioned is Mises's critique of socialism.
The first champions of socialism had 
depicted their ideal society as some sort of a small self-contained egalitarian 
community. Then the classical economists pointed out that living in autarky is 
not very productive. The socialist projects would therefore tend to be islands 
of misery in a capitalist world; and it was very unlikely that many people would 
be attracted by such prospects.
The socialist intellectuals could not 
help but accept this critique, but now they came up with a new idea. They 
claimed that central planning, the characteristic feature of socialism, was more 
productive than the anarchy of the market. It made no sense to establish 
socialism in little islands. What was needed was worldwide central planning, or 
at any rate central planning on as large a scale as possible. This was the state 
of the debate at the end of World War I, when Mises set out to critically 
examine the socialist tenets.
In one of the greatest economics 
articles ever written, Mises once and for all destroyed the claim that central 
planning would make production in society more efficient than the division of 
labor in a market economy. The article had the title "Die Wirtschaftsrechnung im 
sozialistischen Gemeinwesen."
What is a rational allocation of 
resources? The allocation of a resource unit is rational when this unit is used 
in a project that is more important than any other project in which it could 
also have been employed. Hence, the rationality or nonrationality of a resource 
use is to be decided on the basis of a comparison between alternative uses of 
that resource.
Now Mises raised the crucial question: 
What is the standard of comparison? In terms of which criterion can or should we 
compare investment alternatives? Mises pointed out that a market economy could 
use the profitability criterion. For all investments, entrepreneurs can estimate 
the selling proceeds as well as the cost expenditure in terms of money prices. 
And then they can compare the ratios that spring from these 
estimates.
Let us notice that entrepreneurs are 
of course not somehow compelled to only look on profitability when they make 
their decisions. The point is that they can look at the profitability criterion, 
and that in the light of this criterion all investment alternatives in a market 
economy are indeed comparable.
Now what about a socialist economy? 
Mises argued that monetary calculation is here out of the question. For money 
prices can only come into existence in market exchanges, and market exchanges 
presuppose the existence of at least two owners. But in socialism there is only 
one owner of all means of production&#8212;the very definition of socialism&#8212;and thus 
there are no prices for factors of production. It follows that it is impossible, 
in a socialist regime, to calculate a profit rate for any investment project and 
to compare the profitability of different alternative investments.
The central planning agency of a 
socialist society is therefore deprived of the very means of economic 
rationalism. It is confronted by a huge array of heterogeneous resources, 
but it cannot compare the conceivable alternative uses of these resources in 
terms of a common unit. For example, one cannot tell whether 1,000,000 gallons 
of milk are somehow more (or less) than the 1,000 cows that produce this milk, 
just as it is impossible to say whether a castle park is more (or less) than the 
100 gardeners that brought it in shape. All these things are heterogeneous and 
cannot therefore be compared quantitatively&#8212;the problem of adding up apples and 
oranges. For the same reason it is also impossible to tell whether using the 
cows to produce the milk is more efficient than using the gardeners to 
bring the garden in shape.
Only if all of these things are 
exchanged against money can we make such quantitative comparisons, namely, by 
comparing their money prices. It follows that while capitalism is a truly 
rational economic system, socialism is like a huge ship without a compass. Far 
from overcoming the alleged "anarchy of production," socialism actually produces 
more chaos than would have existed without the imposition of central planning. 
Socialism, as Mises would say, is planned chaos.
Epistemology
You might think that, with his 
business cycle theory and his critique of socialism, Mises had stirred up more 
than enough trouble for a lifetime. But I can only encourage all of you to read 
his books, in particular the four great books, very carefully. Each of them is a 
rich mine of insights and arguments. Tonight we cannot do more than go through 
some of the highlights.
Let me therefore move on to another 
one of these highlights: Mises's clarification of the epistemology of economics. 
Mises stated that economic science is a particular branch of a more general 
science&#8212;praxeology, the science of human action. The laws of this science are 
valid a priori, that is, they cannot possibly be refuted or verified by 
any facts that we gather through our senses. They can only be verified or 
refuted by discursive reasoning, which in turn is based on our reflective 
knowledge of what human action is.
Let me give you just one example. 
Consider first the most basic phenomenon that lies at the heart of all modern 
economic theories: human choice. There is absolutely no doubt that human beings 
can make choices and do make choices, and that, if it were not so, it would be 
pointless to engage in economic science at all (and several other disciplines 
such as ethics and law would of course be pointless as well). No school of 
economics disputes this fact, neither the monetarists, nor the supply-siders, 
nor the Walrasians, nor the game theorists, nor the Keynesians (old, new, post, 
and whatever sort of Keynesianism we will get yet).
Now ask yourselves how we come to know 
about the existence of choice. Do we actually observe choices with our eyes? Do 
we hear choices? Do we smell them? Clearly, this is not the case. But this means 
that the most basic phenomenon of economic science is known to us, not by facts 
we gather through our senses, but through an act of reflection on our own 
actions. And the knowledge that we gain this way does therefore not depend on 
information we gather from our senses, and thus it cannot be refuted or verified 
by any such information. It can only be verified or refuted by a more exact 
reflection on the structural features of our actions.
This is why Mises is right in his 
claim that economic science is valid a priori. And all other 
economists, who believe that economics is empirical in the very same sense in 
which for example the natural sciences are empirical are wrong.
Most mainstream economists have never 
given any serious thought to the epistemology of their science. They just repeat 
the slogans of a few academic high priests, who endlessly profess the litany of 
positivism, the doctrine according to which all scientific knowledge comes from 
observed facts or other sense-based methods of fact gathering. These words might 
sound harsh to some of you, but it is no exaggeration to say that positivism, 
despite all beneficial effects it might have had at some point in the past, has 
today become a quasi-religious creed. We can be sure that Auguste Comte, the 
founding father of positivism, now marvels in his grave, because that is exactly 
what he had in mind: replacing Christianity with his brainchild.
This bad new religion does not make 
good weather for the Austrians. Today mainstream economists disdain Mises and 
his followers for shunning empirical work and engaging in the armchair 
gymnastics of a priori theorizing. Many mainstream economists cannot 
pronounce the words "a priori theorizing" without grinding their 
teeth.
Milton Friedman once characterised 
a priori theorizing as a deadly undertaking. If two Austrians disagree, 
according to Friedman, there is only one solution left for them: they have to 
shoot it out.
Now I can assure you that in the ten 
years or so during which I have had the opportunity to observe the Austrians at 
a fairly close distance, it never ever came to a shooting, all the while we 
constantly disagreed with Mises, Rothbard, and amongst ourselves. The Mises 
Institute is located in Alabama, a state blessed with very liberal gun laws. 
There is no problem whatever to go to one of our nice local gun shops, buy a 
decent weapon, and so prepared go to the Mises Summer University or to the 
Austrian Scholar's Conference to apply Friedman's precept. But nobody has ever 
done this.
I therefore think it is high time now 
that Friedman finally accepts the historical record as an empirical refutation 
of his hypothesis. But I doubt he will.
When two Austrians disagree, they do 
not shoot it out; rather, each of them tries to come up with a better argument 
next time, but usually the disagreements remain. Things are not at all different 
in mainstream economics. It is a grave error to believe that empirical field 
studies provide something like a final verdict on a contested question. The 
empirical record shows that disagreements between positivists remain in the face 
of even the most impressive findings.
If anything, therefore, Friedman's 
horror scenario applies with equal right to the positivist camp. If two 
positivists disagree and refuse to accept each other's empirical studies as the 
final word, there remains only one solution: the trigger. But of course this is 
as nonsensical as it is in the case of disagreements between Austrians. Science 
is a process; it is never something like a final state of rest. Disagreements 
are not only unavoidable; they are also necessary and even beneficial to spur 
scientific progress.
So much for Friedman's errors. But 
even many Austrian fellow travelers feel uncomfortable about Mises's views on 
what economics is all about. They encourage students of Austrian Economics to 
leave the ivory tower and apply the theory in empirical work.
This recommendation also rests on 
a serious misunderstanding. Carl Menger, Ludwig von Mises, Murray Rothbard, Hans 
Hoppe, and many other excellent Austrians engage in a priori theorizing 
not because they shun empirical work, but precisely because a priori 
theorizing is the only way to adequately describe certain features of the real 
world, without which it would be impossible to fully understand human behavior 
and to give a scientific underpinning to political decision-making.
If anything, we need not less 
exercises in pure theory, but much more of it. It is true that not everybody is 
born to be a theorist and that applied historical case studies have a great 
pedagogical value. But the future of our science, and thus the future of our 
civilization will depend on the number of young intellectuals willing to learn 
pure theory in the realist tradition of Menger and Mises, and to develop this 
tradition to the best of their abilities.
Realism
This brings us to a final issue. As I 
just said, it is important that we develop praxeology in the realist tradition 
of Menger and Mises. Austrians should not become more like the mainstream, based 
on the false hope that thereby our ideas will become more palatable to 
academics. Turning Austrian economics into just another branch of the mainstream 
will at best flatter the little egos of the protagonists. Austrians should 
become and be all that they can be as the bearers of realist economic theory. 
But they can do this only if they are willing to immerse themselves in the 
tradition of Austrian realism.
This tradition is most vividly present 
in the works of the main line of Austrian theorists: Menger, Böhm-Bawerk, Mises, 
Rothbard, and today in the works of Hans-Hermann Hoppe and the other senior 
fellows of the Mises Institute, as well as in the works of a few others, such as 
Jesús Huerta de Soto, Pascal Salin, and George Reisman. It is less present in 
the works of Friedrich von Wieser, Friedrich von Hayek, and those who, following 
in their footsteps, place too much emphasis on the use of fictitious 
constructions, for example, on the equilibrium construct and on processes of 
equilibration.
The quest for greater realism in the 
social sciences&#8212;this is the core mission of Misesian scholarship in our times. 
At its heart this is a quest for the full truth, and even though we cannot 
expect to ever gain a full picture of anything here on earth, we will try to get 
as close as we can in the coming week. If Misesians remain faithful to their 
mission, it will not fail to yield a rich harvest. For not only the truth, but 
the mere honest quest for realism has a great power of attraction.
It has brought the Austrians important 
converts from the mainstream. For example, at the beginning of the twentieth 
century, Ludwig von Mises himself defected from the mainstream of his time&#8212;the 
Historical School. In the 1970s, Hans-Hermann Hoppe, who is among us tonight, 
defected from the mainstream philosophy of the Frankfurt School; and in the 
1980s, Jeffrey Herbener, also here tonight, defected from neoclassical 
economics.
Today the Austrian School is a vibrant 
and growing movement of economists, historians, philosophers, and other social 
scientists united in their love for the search of truth and in their courage to 
say the truth even if it does not fit the political or academic fashions of our 
day. There is no better place and no better occasion to become acquainted with 
this movement than the Summer University here at the Mises Institute, and I hope 
you will make good use of it.



J.G. Hülsmann is a senior fellow in residence at the Mises Institute. 
<FONT color=#0000ff face="Verdana, Helvetica" 
size=2>JGH@xxxxxxxxx

<A 
href="">[Print 
Friendly Page]
<FONT face=Arial 
size=3> 
<A 
href=""><IMG alt="" border=0 hspace=0 
src="" 
>
 
<A 
href="">Mises Email List 
Services
 
<A 
href="" target=_blank><FONT 
face=Arial>Join the Mises Institute<FONT 
face=Arial> <A href="" 
target=_blank>Mises.org 
Store<FONT 
size=2>
<FONT 
size=2> 
<A 
href="" target=_blank><FONT face=Arial 
size=1>Home | 
<FONT 
face=Arial size=1>About<FONT face=Arial 
size=1> | <A href="" 
target=_blank>Email 
List | <A 
href="" target=_blank><FONT face=Arial 
size=1>Search | 
<FONT 
face=Arial size=1>Contact Us<FONT face=Arial 
size=1> | <A href="" 
target=_blank><FONT face=Arial 
size=1>Periodicals | 
<FONT 
face=Arial size=1>Articles<FONT 
face=Arial> | <A href="" 
target=_blank>Games & 
Fun<A href="" 
target=_blank>News<FONT 
face=Arial size=1> | <A 
href="" target=_blank><FONT face=Arial 
size=1>Resources | 
<FONT 
face=Arial size=1>Catalog<FONT 
face=Arial> | <A 
href="" target=_blank><FONT face=Arial 
size=1>Contributions<FONT 
face=Arial> | <A href="" 
target=_blank>Freedom 
Calendar<FONT 
size=2>


  
  
    You are subscribed as: chaze@xxxxxxxxTo unsubscribe, 
      click here: <A 
      href="">http://mises.biglist.com/unsub.php/article/chaze@xxxxxxxxor 
      e-mail: <A 
      href="">article-unsubscribe-chaze=cvtv.net@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx 
      






Yahoo! Groups Sponsor


  ADVERTISEMENT 









To unsubscribe from this group, send an email to:
realtraders-unsubscribe@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxx





Your use of Yahoo! Groups is subject to the Yahoo! Terms of Service.